I’m lucky to live close to many beautiful urban parks. One of my favourites is a lakeside park that features an open field, some walking trails, playsets for kids, and a swimming dock. Unsurprisingly, it’s very busy in the summertime with visitors of all ages. My question is about music. Some park users set up picnics and bring along portable speakers. I try not to be a grouch about this — it’s a shared space after all and I don’t expect perfect quiet. So: if I asked someone to turn down their music (or turn it off entirely), would I be unduly imposing my own auditory preferences on a public space, or defending the right of other park users to keep their ears free of others’ (sometimes questionable) music choices?
Aesthetic taste is one of the marvels of the human experience. It’s very personal, a means of offering and confirming identity. But it also has the peculiar quality of assuming its own superiority. The German philosopher Immanuel Kant said that judgments of taste contain within them a kind of universal insistence: when I find something beautiful, I am in effect saying that you should too.
ARTICLE CONTINUES BELOW
ARTICLE CONTINUES BELOW
In practice everyone knows that agreement about such things is rare if not impossible. Musical taste in particular varies wildly, and does so aggressively to boot. Blasting tunes in public is a sharp-stick version of the problem of clashing rights and desires. As you note, it often seems that the people most likely to pump up the jam also have the worst possible taste. Weird! So what to do?
Exclude for the moment those go-to-eleven types who bang out deliberately just to annoy other people. They are fiends and should be punished. That still leaves many possible good-faith aesthetic differences in your park scenario. In a train or other confined space, audible music would be a clear violation of a common good. In the moderately sprawling park you describe, the first and best option may be to seek out a quieter corner.
Otherwise, yes, you are imposing your own preferences, including silence. If you feel entitled to do that, be polite and make sure your requests are reasonable. Keep your specific aesthetic judgments to yourself. Be prepared for rebuff, possibly anger. And whatever happens, resist any temptation to smash someone’s expensive boom box, even if you can’t stand Public Enemy’s “Fight the Power†(RIP Radio Raheem, “Do the Right Thing,” 1989).
When entering a grocery store, I noticed a woman sitting outside asking for money and another woman was in the process of giving her some. A few minutes later while in the store, I noticed the same woman who’d been sitting outside grab a jar off a shelf, put it in her bag, then leave the store without paying. Should I have said something?
There’s nothing wrong with asking for money and nothing wrong in giving it. The original transaction here is simple and sound — unless, that is, you object to such use of a public space. Absent that issue, this first exchange is just voluntary charity given in response to open appeal. If the panhandler then decides to supplement the handout with stolen goods, that’s a separate matter.
You might think, knowing the woman now has some ready scratch, that she has a duty use it to purchase the item legitimately. But neither her motivation nor her financial planning are yours to decide. Money is entirely fungible — that’s its point. Once given, there is no moral claim over what happens next. That holds even for the original donor, all the more so for you.
ARTICLE CONTINUES BELOW
ARTICLE CONTINUES BELOW
What is your business is witnessing the act of shoplifting itself. And this might count as a special case. You have evidence that the woman is in straitened circumstances, even if she is momentarily flush. That knowledge bears on your own choices. I suggest that you have a positive reason not to rat her out to the store manager — as you well might any other casual pilferer.
Kant (him again) famously argued that it was never right to steal, even if it was bread to feed your starving family, like Victor Hugo’s miserable Jean Valjean. If you make room for hunger-based exceptions, the argument goes, you undermine the very ideas of property and trust. Well, maybe. Most of us are less strict and more compassionate. It’s one hungry woman and her jar of jam or whatever. Let it go, and finish your own shopping.
Need existential advice from a philosophical adviser? Send your dilemmas and questions to agoodlife@thestar.ca and we’ll guide you to your good life.
Opinion Headlines Newsletter
Take a stand with this regular roundup of the best from our columnists.
Error! Sorry, there was an error processing your request.
There was a problem with the recaptcha. Please try again.
You may unsubscribe at any time. By signing up, you agree to our and . This site is protected by reCAPTCHA and the Google and apply.
Opinion Headlines Newsletter
You’re signed up! You’ll start getting Opinion Headlines in your inbox soon.
Want more of the latest from us? Sign up for more at our newsletter page.
Opinion articles are based on the author’s interpretations and judgments of facts, data and events. More details
Mark Kingwell is a professor of philosophy at the University of
ÎÚÑ»´«Ã½.
To join the conversation set a first and last name in your user profile.
Sign in or register for free to join the Conversation